Cantor's Theorem
Theorem
There is no surjection from a set $S$ to its power set for any set $S$.
That is, $S$ is strictly smaller than its power set.
Proof 1
Aiming for a contradiction, suppose $S$ is a set with a surjection $f: S \to \powerset S$.
Then:
\(\ds \forall x \in S: \, \) | \(\ds \map f x\) | \(\in\) | \(\ds \powerset S\) | by hypothesis | ||||||||||
\(\ds \leadsto \ \ \) | \(\ds \forall x \in S: \, \) | \(\ds \map f x\) | \(\subseteq\) | \(\ds S\) | Definition of Power Set |
Now by Law of Excluded Middle, there are two choices for every $x \in S$:
- $x \in \map f x$
- $x \notin \map f x$
Let $T = \set {x \in S: x \notin \map f x}$.
As $f$ is supposed to be a surjection, $\exists a \in S: T = \map f a$.
Thus:
- $a \in \map f a \implies a \notin \map f a$
- $a \notin \map f a \implies a \in \map f a$
This is a contradiction, so the initial supposition that there is such a surjection must be false.
$\blacksquare$
Law of the Excluded Middle
This proof depends on the Law of the Excluded Middle.
This is one of the axioms of logic that was determined by Aristotle, and forms part of the backbone of classical (Aristotelian) logic.
However, the intuitionist school rejects the Law of the Excluded Middle as a valid logical axiom.
This in turn invalidates this proof from an intuitionistic perspective.
Proof 2
Let $S$ be a set.
Let $\powerset {S}$ be the power set of $S$.
Let $f: S \to \powerset {S}$ be a mapping.
Let $T = \left\{{x \in S: \neg \left({x \in \map f x}\right)}\right\}$.
Then $T \subseteq S$, so $T \in \powerset {S}$ by the definition of power set.
We will show that $T$ is not in the image of $f$ and therefore $f$ is not surjective.
Aiming for a contradiction, suppose:
- $\exists a \in S: T = \map f a$
Suppose that:
- $a \in \map f a$
Then by the definition of $T$:
- $\neg \left({a \in T}\right)$
Thus since $T = f \left({a}\right)$:
- $\neg \left({a \in \map f a }\right)$
- $(1) \quad a \in \map f a \implies \neg \left({ a \in \map f a }\right)$
Suppose instead that:
- $\neg \left({a \in \map f a}\right)$
Then by the definition of $T$:
- $a \in T$
Thus since $T = f \left({a}\right)$:
- $a \in \map f a$
- $(2) \quad \neg \left({ a \in \map f a }\right) \implies a \in \map f a$
By Non-Equivalence of Proposition and Negation, applied to $(1)$ and $(2)$, this is a contradiction.
As the specific choice of $a$ did not matter, we derive a contradiction by Existential Instantiation.
Thus by Proof by Contradiction, the supposition that $\exists a \in S: T = \map f a$ must be false.
It follows that $f$ is not a surjection.
$\blacksquare$
Also see
Compare this with Russell's Paradox.
Source of Name
This entry was named for Georg Cantor.
Sources
- 1965: Seth Warner: Modern Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $\text {III}$: The Natural Numbers: $\S 17$: Finite Sets: Exercise $17.14$
- 1971: Gaisi Takeuti and Wilson M. Zaring: Introduction to Axiomatic Set Theory: $\S 10.4$ $\S 10.5$
- 1972: A.G. Howson: A Handbook of Terms used in Algebra and Analysis ... (previous) ... (next): $\S 4$: Number systems $\text{I}$: A set-theoretic approach
- 1978: Thomas A. Whitelaw: An Introduction to Abstract Algebra ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $4$: Mappings: Exercise $11$
- 2010: Raymond M. Smullyan and Melvin Fitting: Set Theory and the Continuum Problem (revised ed.) ... (previous) ... (next): Chapter $1$: General Background: $\S 4$ Larger and smaller: Theorem $4.1$ (Cantor's theorem)