Euclid's Lemma for Unique Factorization Domain
Lemma
Let $\struct {D, +, \times}$ be a unique factorization domain.
Let $p$ be an irreducible element of $D$.
Let $a, b \in D$ such that:
- $p \divides a \times b$
where $\divides$ means is a divisor of.
Then $p \divides a$ or $p \divides b$.
General Result
Let $p$ be an irreducible element of $D$.
Let $n \in D$ such that:
- $\ds n = \prod_{i \mathop = 1}^r a_i$
where $a_i \in D$ for all $i: 1 \le i \le r$.
Then if $p$ divides $n$, it follows that $p$ divides $a_i$ for some $i$.
That is:
- $p \divides a_1 a_2 \ldots a_n \implies p \divides a_1 \lor p \divides a_2 \lor \cdots \lor p \divides a_n$
Proof
The elements $a$ and $b$ have complete factorizations:
- $a = u \times x_1 \times x_2 \times \cdots \times x_n$
and
- $b = v \times y_1 \times y_2 \times \cdots \times y_m$
where $u$ and $v$ are units of $D$ and $x_1, x_2, \ldots, x_n$ and $y_1, y_2, \ldots, y_m$ are irreducible elements.
Then the unique complete factorization of $a \times b$ into irreducible elements is:
- $(1): \quad a \times b = \paren {u \times v} \times x_1 \times x_2 \times \cdots \times x_n \times y_1 \times y_2 \times \cdots \times y_m$
If $p$ is an associate of $x_i$ for some $i$ then we will have $p \divides a$.
Similarly, if $p$ is an associate of $y_i$ for some $i$ then $p \divides b$.
Aiming for a contradiction, suppose that $p$ is not an associate of $x_i$ or $y_i$ for all $i$.
Since $p \divides a \times b$, there is a $c \in D$ such that $p \times c = a \times b$.
This element $c$ has the unique complete factorization:
- $c = w \times z_1 \times z_2 \times \cdots \times z_l$
where $w$ is a unit of $D$ and $z_1, z_2, \ldots, z_l$ are irreducible elements.
This gives us another complete factorization:
- $a \times b = w \times p \times z_1 \times z_2 \times \cdots \times z_l$
But the complete factorization $(1)$ contains no irreducible element that is an associate of $p$.
This contradicts the unique factorization of $a \times b$.
We conclude that $p$ is an associate of $x_i$ or $y_i$ for some $i$.
Therefore, $p \divides a$ or $p \divides b$.
$\blacksquare$
Source of Name
This entry was named for Euclid.
Also see
![]() | This page has been identified as a candidate for refactoring of medium complexity. In particular: These results could/should all be interlinked appropriately. Or perhaps an overview page transcluding all of them. Until this has been finished, please leave {{Refactor}} in the code.
New contributors: Refactoring is a task which is expected to be undertaken by experienced editors only. Because of the underlying complexity of the work needed, it is recommended that you do not embark on a refactoring task until you have become familiar with the structural nature of pages of $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$.To discuss this page in more detail, feel free to use the talk page. When this work has been completed, you may remove this instance of {{Refactor}} from the code. |
- Euclid's Lemma for Prime Divisors, for the usual statement of this result, which is this lemma as applied specifically to the integers.
- Euclid's Lemma for Irreducible Elements is the same result when $D$ is a Euclidean Domain.