Transfinite Recursion Theorem/Theorem 1
![]() | This article needs to be linked to other articles. In particular: Just a few to be tidied up You can help $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$ by adding these links. To discuss this page in more detail, feel free to use the talk page. When this work has been completed, you may remove this instance of {{MissingLinks}} from the code. |
Theorem
Let $G$ be a (class) mapping from $\On^{\On}$ to $\On$.
Let $K$ be a class of mappings $f$ that satisfy:
where $f {\restriction_x}$ denotes the restriction of $f$ to $x$.
Let $F = \bigcup K$ be the union of $K$.
Then:
- $(1): \quad F$ is a mapping with domain $\On$
- $(2): \quad \forall x \in \On: \map F x = \map G {F {\restriction_x} }$
- $(3): \quad F$ is unique. That is, if another mapping $A$ has the above two properties, then $A = F$.
Corollary
Let $x$ be an ordinal.
Let $G$ be a mapping
There exists a unique mapping $f$ that satisfies the following properties:
- The domain of $f$ is $x$
- $\forall y \in x: \map f y = \map G {f \restriction y}$
Proof
First a lemma:
Lemma
Let $f$ be a mapping with a domain $y$ where $y$ is an ordinal.
Let $f$ satisfy the condition that:
- $\forall x \in y: \map f x = \map G {f \restriction x}$
where $f \restriction x$ denotes the restriction of $f$ to $x$.
Let $g$ be a mapping with a domain $z$ where $z$ is an ordinal.
Let $g$ satisfy the condition that:
- $\forall x \in z: \map g x = \map G {g \restriction x}$
Let $y \subseteq z$.
Then:
- $\forall x \in y: \map f x = \map g x$
$\Box$
$K$ is a chain
First, it is necessary to show that $K$ is a chain of mappings under the subset relation.
![]() | This article, or a section of it, needs explaining. In particular: Might be worth setting up a page defining exactly what a "chain of mappings" actually is in concrete terms You can help $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$ by explaining it. To discuss this page in more detail, feel free to use the talk page. When this work has been completed, you may remove this instance of {{Explain}} from the code. |
Take any $f, g \in K$.
Set $B$ equal to the domain of $f$ and set $C$ equal to the domain of $g$.
From Relation between Two Ordinals:
- $B \subseteq C \lor C \subseteq B$
From Lemma 1:
- $\forall x \in B \cap C: \map f x = \map g x$
So depending on whether $B \subseteq C$ or $C \subseteq B$:
- $f \subseteq g \lor g \subseteq f$
From Subset Relation is Ordering, it follows that $\subseteq$ is a total ordering on $K$.
$\Box$
Domain of $F$ is an ordinal
Since the union of a chain of mappings is a mapping, $F$ is a mapping.
Moreover, $\forall x \in B: \map f x = \map F x$, because $F$ is an extension of the mapping $f$.
The domain of $F$ is a subset of the class of all ordinals because it is the union of a collection of mappings whose domains are themselves subsets of ordinals.
\(\ds a\) | \(\in\) | \(\ds \Dom F\) | ||||||||||||
\(\, \ds \land \, \) | \(\ds x\) | \(\in\) | \(\ds a\) | |||||||||||
\(\ds \leadsto \ \ \) | \(\ds \exists f: \exists \beta \in \On: \, \) | \(\ds f\) | \(:\) | \(\ds \beta \to \Img f\) | Definition of $F$ (above) | |||||||||
\(\, \ds \land \, \) | \(\ds a\) | \(\in\) | \(\ds \beta\) | |||||||||||
\(\ds \leadsto \ \ \) | \(\ds a\) | \(\in\) | \(\ds \On\) | Transitivity of $\beta$ and $\On$ | ||||||||||
\(\, \ds \land \, \) | \(\ds x\) | \(\in\) | \(\ds \beta\) | |||||||||||
\(\ds \leadsto \ \ \) | \(\ds x\) | \(\in\) | \(\ds \Dom F\) |
From this it follows that $\Dom F$ is an ordinal, since it is a transitive subset of $\On$.
Domain of $F$ is $\On$
Assume the domain of $F$ is a set.
Since $F$ is a mapping, the range of $F$ is a set and $F$ is a set.
Then $\Dom F = \gamma$ for some ordinal $\gamma$.
Define $C$ as follows:
- $C = F \cup \set {\tuple {\gamma, \map G {F {\restriction_\gamma} } } }$
Then $C$ is a mapping with domain $\gamma^+$ and satisfies:
- $\forall x < \gamma^+: \map C x = \map G {F {\restriction_\gamma} }$
Therefore $C$ is a member of $K$ (note that $F {\restriction_\gamma} = C {\restriction_\gamma}$).
- $\ds C \in K \implies C \subseteq \bigcup K$
So $C \subseteq F$.
But if $F$ is a set, $F \subsetneq C$, a contradiction.
Therefore, $\Dom F$ cannot be a set and must therefore be the set of all ordinals $\On$.
$\Box$
Value of $F$ is $\map G {F {\restriction_\alpha} }$
- $\forall x \in \On: \exists f \in K: \map f x = \map F x$
Since $f \in K$:
- $\map f x = \map G {f {\restriction_x} }$
But $\forall y < x: \map f y = \map F y$, so by Equality of Restrictions:
- $f {\restriction_x} = F {\restriction_x}$
Therefore:
- $\map F \alpha = \map G {F {\restriction_\alpha} }$
$\Box$
$F$ is Unique
Finally, assume there is another mapping $H$ that satisfies the first two properties.
Then $H$ is equal to $F$ by transfinite induction:
\(\ds \forall x \in y: \, \) | \(\ds \map H x\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \map F x\) | |||||||||||
\(\ds \leadsto \ \ \) | \(\ds \paren {H \restriction y}\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \paren {F \restriction y}\) | Equality of Restrictions | ||||||||||
\(\ds \leadsto \ \ \) | \(\ds \map G {H \restriction y}\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \map G {F \restriction y}\) | by hypothesis | ||||||||||
\(\ds \leadsto \ \ \) | \(\ds \map H y\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \map F y\) | by hypothesis |
So for all ordinals:
- $\map H y = \map F y$
Thus:
- $H = F$
$\blacksquare$
Also see