Non-Finite Cardinal is equal to Cardinal Product
Theorem
Let $\omega$ denote the minimally inductive set.
Let $x$ be an ordinal such that $x \ge \omega$.
Then:
- $\card x = \card {x \times x}$
where $\times$ denotes the Cartesian product.
Corollary
Let $S$ be a set that is equinumerous to its cardinal number.
Let $\card S$ denote the cardinal number of $S$.
Let:
- $\card S \ge \omega$
where $\omega$ denotes the minimally inductive set.
Then:
- $\card {S \times S} = \card S$
Proof
The proof shall proceed by Transfinite Induction on $x$.
Let:
- $\forall y \in x: y < \omega \lor \card y = \card {y \times y}$
There are two cases:
Case 1: $\card y = \card x$ for some $y \in x$
If this is so, then:
\(\ds \card x\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \card y\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds \) | \(=\) | \(\ds \card {y \times y}\) | Inductive hypothesis | |||||||||||
\(\ds \) | \(=\) | \(\ds \card {x \times x}\) |
$\Box$
Case 2: $\card y < \card x$ for all $y \in x$
We have that either:
- $y < \omega$
or:
- $\card y = \card {y + 1}$
In either case, we have that:
- $\card {y + 1} < \card x$
and therefore:
- $y + 1 \in x$
Therefore, $x$ is a limit ordinal.
Let $R_0$ denote the canonical order of $\On^2$.
Let $J_0$ be defined as the unique order isomorphism between $\On^2$ and $\On$ as defined in canonical order.
![]() | This article needs to be linked to other articles. In particular: The above section Definition:Canonical Order#Properties no longer exists. Instead, this link is to go to the (not yet established) second definition of Canonical Order. You can help $\mathsf{Pr} \infty \mathsf{fWiki}$ by adding these links. To discuss this page in more detail, feel free to use the talk page. When this work has been completed, you may remove this instance of {{MissingLinks}} from the code. |
It follows that:
- $\ds \map {J_0} {x \times x} = \bigcup_{y \mathop \in x} \bigcup_{z \mathop \in x} \map {J_0} {y, z}$
But moreover:
\(\ds \map {J_0} {y, z}\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \map {\in^{-1} } {\map {J_0} {y, z} }\) | Definition of Preimage of Element under Mapping | |||||||||||
\(\ds \) | \(=\) | \(\ds \map {J_0} {\map {R_0^{-1} } {y, z} }\) | as $J_0$ forms an Order Isomorphism. |
Since $J_0$ is a bijection:
\(\ds \card {\map {J_0} {y, z} }\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \card {\map {J_0} {\map {R_0^{-1} } {y, z} } }\) | Equality shown above | |||||||||||
\(\ds \) | \(=\) | \(\ds \card {\map {R_0^{-1} } {y, z} }\) | Image of Bijection Cardinal Equality |
Take $\max \set {y, z}$.
\(\ds \tuple {a, b}\) | \(\in\) | \(\ds \map {R_0^{-1} } {y, z}\) | by hypothesis | |||||||||||
\(\ds \leadstoandfrom \ \ \) | \(\ds \tuple {a, b}\) | \(R_0\) | \(\ds \tuple {y, z}\) | Definition of Image of Element under Mapping | ||||||||||
\(\ds \leadstoandfrom \ \ \) | \(\ds a, b\) | \(\le\) | \(\ds \max \set {y, z}\) | Definition of Canonical Order | ||||||||||
\(\ds \leadstoandfrom \ \ \) | \(\ds a, b\) | \(\in\) | \(\ds \max \set {y, z} + 1\) | Definition of Successor Set |
It follows that:
\(\ds \card {\map {R_0^{-1} } {y, z} }\) | \(\le\) | \(\ds \card {\max \set {y, z} + 1 \times \max \set {y, z} + 1}\) | ||||||||||||
\(\ds \) | \(=\) | \(\ds \card {\max \set {y, z} + 1}\) | Inductive hypothesis | |||||||||||
\(\ds \) | \(<\) | \(\ds \card x\) | by hypothesis for the case |
Therefore:
- $\card {\map {R_0^{-1} } {y, z} } < \card x$
Thus by Cardinal Inequality implies Ordinal Inequality:
- $\forall y, z \in x: \map {J_0} {y, z} < \card x$
It follows by Supremum Inequality for Ordinals that:
- $\map {J_0} {x \times x} \subseteq \card x$
Hence:
\(\ds \card {x \times x}\) | \(=\) | \(\ds \card {\map {J_0} {x \times x} }\) | Image of Bijection Cardinal Equality | |||||||||||
\(\ds \) | \(\le\) | \(\ds \card x\) | Subset of Ordinal implies Cardinal Inequality |
But also by Set Less than Cardinal Product:
- $\card x \le \card {x \times x}$
Thus:
- $\card x = \card {x \times x}$
$\blacksquare$
Sources
- 1971: Gaisi Takeuti and Wilson M. Zaring: Introduction to Axiomatic Set Theory: $\S 10.33$