Ordering can be Expanded to compare Additional Pair

From ProofWiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Theorem

Let $\struct {S, \preceq}$ be an ordered set.

Let $a$ and $b$ be non-comparable elements of $S$.

That is, let:

$a \not\preceq b$

and:

$b \not\preceq a$


Let ${\preceq'} = {\preceq} \cup \set {\tuple {a, b} }$.

Let $\preceq'^+$ be the transitive closure of $\preceq'$.


Then:

$\preceq'^+$ is an ordering.


$\preceq'^+$ can be defined by letting $p \preceq'^+ q$ if and only if:

$p \preceq q$ or
$p \preceq a$ and $b \preceq q$.


Proof 1

$\preceq'^+$ is a superset of $\preceq$.

By Relation Contains Diagonal Relation iff Reflexive:

$\Delta_S \subseteq \preceq$

where $\Delta_S$ denotes the diagonal relation.

By Subset Relation is Transitive it follows that:

$\Delta_S \subseteq \preceq'^+$

By Relation Contains Diagonal Relation iff Reflexive, it follows that $\preceq'^+$ is reflexive.

$\Box$


$\preceq'^+$ is transitive by the definition of transitive closure as the smallest transitive superset.

$\Box$


Next we will establish that if $x \preceq'^+ y$ then either $x \preceq y$ or $x \preceq a$ and $b \preceq y$.

Let $x, y \in S$ and let $x \preceq'^+ y$.

By the finite chain definition of transitive closure, for some $n \in \N_{>0}$ there are $x_0, x_1, \dots, x_n$ such that:

$x_0 = x$
$x_n = y$
$(1): \quad x_0 \preceq' x_1 \preceq' \cdots \preceq' x_n$

Assume that this sequence between $x_0$ and $x_n$ is as short as possible.

That is, let $n$ be the smallest number such that such a sequence exists.

In $(1)$, at most one of the relations can be $a \preceq' b$:

If there were a segment of the form $a \preceq' b \preceq' \cdots \preceq' a \preceq' b$, then the sequence could be shortened by replacing that with $a \preceq' b$.

Thus $(1)$ takes one of these forms:

$(a): \quad x_0 \preceq x_1 \preceq \cdots \preceq x_n$
$(b): \quad x_0 \preceq \cdots \preceq x_j \preceq a \preceq' b \preceq x_{j+3} \preceq \cdots \preceq x_n$

If $(a)$, Transitive Chaining shows that:

$x_0 \preceq x_n$

That is, $x \preceq y$.

If $(b)$, Transitive Chaining shows that:

$x_0 \preceq a \preceq' b \preceq x_n$

That is, $x \preceq a$ and $b \preceq y$.

So whenever $x \preceq'^+ y$, either:

$x \preceq y$ or both
$x \preceq a$ and $b \preceq y$

$\Box$


Aiming for a contradiction, suppose that $x \preceq'^+ y$, $y \preceq'^+ x$, and $x \ne y$.

By the above, we must have:

$(1a): \quad x \preceq y$ or both
$(1b): \quad x \preceq a$ and $b \preceq y$
$(2a): \quad y \preceq x$ or both
$(2b): \quad y \preceq a$ and $b \preceq x$.

If $(1a)$ and $(2a)$ hold, then $x \preceq y$ and $y \preceq x$.

Thus $x = y$ by antisymmetry of $\preceq$, contradicting the assumption that $x \ne y$.

If $(1b)$ and $(2a)$ hold, then $b \preceq y$, and $y \preceq x$, and $x \preceq a$.

By Transitive Chaining, $b \preceq a$.

This contradicts the premise that $a$ and $b$ are non-comparable.

A similar contradiction results if $(1a)$ and $(2b)$ hold.

If $(1b)$ and $(2b)$ hold, then $b \preceq x$ and $x \preceq a$.

Thus by transitivity, $b \preceq a$.

This contradicts the premise that $a$ and $b$ are non-comparable.


We have shown that assuming $\preceq'^+$ is not antisymmetric leads to a contradiction, so

$\preceq'^+$ is antisymmetric.

$\Box$


Since $\preceq'^+$ is transitive and antisymmetric, it is an ordering.

We must now show that for $p, q \in S$, $p \preceq'^+ q$ if and only if:

$p \preceq q$ or
$p \preceq a$ and $b \preceq q$.

We have already shown above that $p \preceq'^+ q$ implies one of these conditions.

We now prove the converse.

Suppose that $p \preceq q$.

Then $p \preceq' q$ by Set is Subset of Union.

By the definition of transitive closure:

$p \preceq'^+ q$

Suppose instead that $p \preceq a$ and $a \preceq q$.

Then by Set is Subset of Union and the definition of $\preceq'$:

$p \preceq' a$
$a \preceq' b$
$b \preceq' q$

Thus by the definition of transitive closure:

$p \preceq'^+ a$
$a \preceq'^+ b$
$b \preceq'^+ q$

Since the transitive closure is transitive, Transitive Chaining shows that $p \preceq'^+ q$.

Thus the statement that $p \preceq'^+ q$ is equivalent to the conditions described in the theorem statement.

$\blacksquare$


Proof 2

Let $\prec$ be the reflexive reduction of $\preceq$.

Let $\prec' = {\prec} \cup \set {\tuple {a, b} }$.

By Reflexive Reduction of Ordering is Strict Ordering, $\prec$ is a strict ordering.

Define a relation $\prec'_2$ by letting $p \prec'_2 q$ if and only if:

$p \prec q$ or
$p \preceq a$ and $b \preceq q$

By Strict Ordering can be Expanded to Compare Additional Pair, $\prec'_2$ is a strict ordering and is the transitive closure of $\prec'$.

Then the reflexive closure of $\prec'_2$, ${\prec'_2}^=$ is the transitive reflexive closure of $\prec'$.

From Equivalence of Definitions of Reflexive Transitive Closure, ${\prec'_2}^=$ is the transitive closure of the reflexive closure of $\prec'$.

The reflexive closure of $\prec'$ is $\preceq'$, so ${\prec'_2}^=$ is the transitive closure of $\preceq'$.

But ${\prec'_2}^=$ is clearly the relation defined by the two conditions in the theorem statement.

$\blacksquare$