Thomae Function is Continuous at Irrational Numbers/Lemma

From ProofWiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Lemma for Thomae Function is Continuous at Irrational Numbers

In the following it is to be understood that all rational numbers expressed in the form $\dfrac p q$ are in canonical form.


Let $x \in \R \setminus \Q$.

Let $\Q$ be ordered in the following way:

$\dfrac {p_1} {q_1} \prec \dfrac {p_2} {q_2} \iff \begin {cases} q_1 < q_2 & : q_1 \ne q_2 \\ p_1 < p_2 & : q_1 = q_2 \end {cases}$

and so we can denote $\Q$ with this ordering as $\struct {\Q, \prec}$


Let $q \in \Z_{>0}$ be a positive integer.

Let $S \subseteq \struct {\Q, \prec}$ defined as:

$S = \set {z \in \Q: z \prec \dfrac 1 q}$

That is, $S$ is the set of all rational numbers whose denominators are all less than or equal to $q$.


Let $a$ be the supremum of the set:

$\set {z \in S: z < x}$

Let $b$ be the infimum of the set:

$\set {z \in S: x < z}$

Then we have that the open interval:

$C = \openint a b$

contains $x$ and no rational numbers whose denominators are less than $q$.


Proof

Let $F := \floor x$ be the floor of $x$.

Let $C := \ceiling x$ be the ceiling of $x$.


Consider the interval:

$I = \closedint F C$

As $x$ is irrational, we have that:

$F < x < C$

and so:

$x \in I$

Because $F$ and $C$ are integers by definition, they can be expressed as:

$F = \dfrac F 1$
$C = \dfrac C 1$

and so $F, C \in S$

Let $r \le q$.

Consider the set $S_r$:

$S_r = \set {F, F + \dfrac 1 r, F + \dfrac 2 r, \ldots, F + \dfrac {r - 1} r, C}$

which is a finite set of rational numbers.

We have that:

$I = S_1 \cup S_2 \cup S_3 \cup \cdots \cup S_{q - 1} \cup S_q$

and so it follows that $I$ is itself finite.

Then we have that:

\(\ds a = \sup \set {z \in S: z < x}\) \(=\) \(\ds \sup \set {z \in I: z < x}\)
\(\ds b = \inf \set {z \in S: x < z}\) \(=\) \(\ds \inf \set {z \in I: x < z}\)

But as $I$ is finite, then so are $\set {z \in I: z < x}$ and $\set {z \in I: x < z}$.

Because $F \in \set {z \in I: z < x}$ and $C \in \set {z \in I: x < z}$ we have that neither $\set {z \in I: z < x}$ nor $\set {z \in I: x < z}$ are empty.

Hence from Finite Subset of Ordered Set contains Supremum:

$a \in \set {z \in I: z < x}$

and from Finite Subset of Ordered Set contains Infimum:

$b \in \set {z \in I: x < z}$

Hence $\exists a, b, \in S: a < x < b$

It follows from the construction that there are no elements of $S$ in \openint a b$.

$\blacksquare$