Equivalence of Definitions of Prime Ideal of Commutative and Unitary Ring

From ProofWiki
Jump to navigation Jump to search

Theorem

The following definitions of the concept of Prime Ideal of Commutative and Unitary Ring are equivalent:

Definition 1

A prime ideal of $R$ is a proper ideal $P$ such that:

$\forall a, b \in R : a \circ b \in P \implies a \in P$ or $b \in P$

Definition 2

A prime ideal of $R$ is a proper ideal $P$ of $R$ such that:

$I \circ J \subseteq P \implies I \subseteq P \text { or } J \subseteq P$

for all ideals $I$ and $J$ of $R$.

Definition 3

A prime ideal of $R$ is a proper ideal $P$ of $R$ such that:

the complement $R \setminus P$ of $P$ in $R$ is closed under the ring product $\circ$.


Proof

Let $\struct {R, +, \circ}$ be a commutative and unitary ring throughout.

$(1)$ implies $(2)$

Let $P$ be a prime ideal of $R$ by definition 1.

Then by definition:

$\forall a, b \in R : a \circ b \in P \implies a \in P$ or $b \in P$

Let $I \circ J \subseteq P$.

Aiming for a contradiction, suppose that both $I \nsubseteq P$ and $J \nsubseteq P$.

Then by definition of subset:

$\exists a \in I \setminus P, b \in J \setminus P$

But by definition of subset product

$a \circ b \in P$ as $I \circ J \subseteq P$

Thus we have $a, b \in P$ such that:

$a \circ b \in P$ where $a \notin P$ and $b \notin P$

But this contradicts the criterion for $P$ to be a prime ideal of $R$ by definition 1

Thus by Proof by Contradiction, either $I \subseteq P$ or $J \subseteq P$,

Thus $P$ is a prime ideal of $R$ by definition 2.

$\Box$


$(2)$ implies $(1)$

Let $P$ be a prime ideal of $R$ by definition 2.

Then by definition:

$I \circ J \subseteq P \implies I \subseteq P \text { or } J \subseteq P$

for all ideals $I$ and $J$ of $R$.

Let $a, b \in R$ such that $a \circ b \in P$.

Consider $\ideal a$ and $\ideal b$, the ideals generated by $a$ and $b$.

Let $r \in \ideal a, s \in \ideal b$.

Then:

$\exists m, n \in R: r = m \circ a, s = n \circ b$

Therefore:

\(\ds r \circ s\) \(=\) \(\ds \paren {m \circ a} \circ \paren {n \circ b}\)
\(\ds \) \(=\) \(\ds \paren {m \circ n} \circ \paren {a \circ b}\) Definition of Commutative Ring
\(\ds \) \(\in\) \(\ds P\) Definition of Ideal of Ring: $m \circ n \in R$, $a \circ b \in P$

This shows that $\ideal a \circ \ideal b \subseteq P$.

By definition 2, $\ideal a \subseteq P$ or $\ideal b \subseteq P$.

This implies $a \in P$ or $b \in P$.

Thus $P$ is a prime ideal of $R$ by definition 1.

$\Box$


$(1)$ implies $(3)$

Let $P$ be a prime ideal of $R$ by definition 1.

Then by definition:

$\forall a, b \in R : a \circ b \in P \implies a \in P$ or $b \in P$

Aiming for a contradiction, suppose $R \setminus P$ is not multiplicatively closed.

That is:

\(\ds \exists a, b \in R \setminus P: \, \) \(\ds a \circ b\) \(\notin\) \(\ds R \setminus P\)
\(\ds \leadsto \ \ \) \(\ds a \circ b\) \(\in\) \(\ds P\)
\(\ds \leadsto \ \ \) \(\ds a\) \(\in\) \(\ds P\)
\(\, \ds \lor \, \) \(\ds b\) \(\in\) \(\ds P\)


But this contradicts the assertion that $a, b \in R \setminus P$.

Thus by Proof by Contradiction $R \setminus P$ is multiplicatively closed.

Thus $P$ is a prime ideal of $R$ by definition 3.

$\Box$


$(3)$ implies $(1)$

Let $P$ be a prime ideal of $R$ by definition 3.

Then by definition:

the complement $R \setminus P$ of $P$ in $R$ is closed under the ring product $\circ$.

Aiming for a contradiction, suppose let $a \circ b \in P$ such that $a \notin P$ and $b \notin P$.

Then:

$a, b \in R \setminus P$

by definition of relative complement.

But $R \setminus P$ is closed under the ring product $\circ$.

That means:

$\forall a, b \in R \setminus P \implies a \circ b \in R \setminus P $

But this contradicts the assertion that $a \circ b \in P$.

Thus by Proof by Contradiction either $a \in P$ or $b \in P$ (or both).

Thus $P$ is a prime ideal of $R$ by definition 1.

$\blacksquare$